An Irrefutable Definition of Natural Rights

The earth was the center of the universe for a long time. When we finally broke through that error, we got a perspective that eventually put a man on the moon. Likewise, the unspoken but widely accepted restriction of rights to humans, or at least to sentient creatures, has kept us from the universal truth, viz., all things have rights. Every natural object has natural rights.

This discovery came as a result of thinking that there ought to be a basis for natural rights within natural law. Then Einstein’s admonition to “Look deep into nature, and then you will understand everything better” seemed the perfect methodology. It took a while to find natural rights in nature, but eventually, I had the “yes, of course” moment.

We have overlooked this insight because natural rights are profoundly ubiquitous, and like a fish doesn’t know he is wet, we have missed what was in plain sight everywhere we looked.

What is a Right Anyway?

The idea of “rights” is clearly one of authority. Even toddlers demonstrate this sense when you violate their authority and take away their toy. Then there’s that feeling we all experience and youths verbalize it with “You aren’t the boss of me.” The idea of “a right” to do or have something is clearly an abstract one, but natural rights are always connected intimately to something physical or mental.

It is insightful to take the perspective of an outsider watching a rights-holder. What we see is someone who has a warrant, an authorization, an empowerment, or an authority to act for, or to be an agent for himself. In other words, having the power (capability) to act is also having the power (authority) to act. The two characteristics cannot be separated. Let me simplify this.

Ontologically: the nature of nature is such that natural things have agency within nature to do what they naturally do.

We know that objects have natural rights because we see them exerting that authority over themselves and other objects.

It troubles me that these explications complicate something so profoundly simple. Try to stop thinking words and just pause a moment on these visions where you will see authority and capability simultaneously:

the sun holding the earth in orbit,

a beaver cutting down a tree,

a child solving a puzzle.

When we view the universe through this quiet lens, we have a spiritual experience. The universe becomes a living thing with beauty, majesty, and power.

This is Important

Western civilization rotates on an axis of natural rights. This becomes apparent if one removes the idea from our culture and watches what happens. Freedom and justice disappear and chaos rules. Chaos rules in pockets of our civilization where rights are deliberately violated to create uncertainty and fear as a means to control the vulnerable human spirit.

An improved understanding of natural rights can provide a stronger, irrefutable claim to the sanctity of natural rights and stop bad actors who ride atheism into power. This new vision of natural rights appears in a purely secular definition and is therefore incapable of dismissal based on the religious tenets of these types. Meanwhile, it is not a negation of Divine Providence but an explanation of how the Creator endowed natural rights.

The Terse, Universal Definition of Natural Rights

Natural Rights: the authority of an operator to operate.

The Long Version

“Natural Rights” is the label we abstract from and then apply to the authority or agency an operator possesses to exercise its capabilities. For example, I have the power to speak, and my authority to speak is inherent and intrinsic within that power. When I speak, I exercise my ability and my right simultaneously because that right is inalienable. It cannot be separated from my power to speak. If you thwart my ability, you also destroy my right. You either have a speaker with the natural right to speak, or you have neither.

The right to life, or more broadly, the right to exist, creates a space filled by the right to operate.

The Explication

Because a right is an abstract idea, it must have a real antecedent, or else it has no standing. Its antecedent is the power/authority exhibited by an entity when it exercises that power/authority. That statement may seem circular, but only because Temporal Rights are profoundly inherent and intrinsic. One can, with semantic grace, denote a right as being the “authority” aspect of the corresponding capability.

For example, the capability to own property inherently includes the right to own property: without that right, ownership is meaningless. In this particular example there is a clear connection to law and jurisprudence.

The Unification of Authorities

Temporal Rights are inherent, intrinsic, and inalienable in a manner more profound than any traditional theory of natural rights. The distance between temporal rights and the laws of nature and hence also natural law could not be shorter. They are indeed one and the same.

This is how the Creator endowed “unalienable rights”.

This is usurpassable intrinsically.

This is an irrefutable definition of natural rights.

Why “Temporal Rights”

I use the name “Temporal Rights”, primarily because they are created in the instant of the creation of an operator and are extinguished in the moment of its demise.

The Abstraction We Call Freedom is not an Abstraction

To fully comprehend this “temporal rights” paradigm for natural rights we need to realize that the idea of “rights” is an abstract one. There is no self-existent object we can call “a right”, only the operator itself has self-existence. To be a correct abstraction, it must have an antecedent, something from which we draw out the abstraction. For the human being, it is the ability to choose that gives rise to the right to choose, or as we often say, “the freedom to choose”. This freedom is evident in physical behavior.

The punishable abuse of rights is the essence of good government, and Temporal RIghts makes these matters more tangible and hence more enforceable.

Freedom and justice provide an environment where the human being can have confidence in the efficacy of the sacrifices required by progress. Temporal Rights theory did not create this relationship, but it does anchor it in natural law.

The Ascendency of Temporal Rights

The natural law that governs the operator and the natural rights that arise therein are in the same domain. There is no need for a theory to connect them. There is no need for logical arguments or for “reason” to be cited for the derivation of these rights or for appeals to related observations of human behaviors and values.

Traditional theories of natural rights typically claim a connection to natural law. The Temporal Rights paradigm says that natural rights are not merely connected, but an intrinsic characteristic of the laws of nature. There is no claim for natural rights that is more natural than this.

The sum and substance of years of natural rights theory reach their climax in Temporal Rights.

Good and Evil

The law of the jungle is played out on the Serengeti and in the ghettos, where untamed, uncivilized creatures consume one another. The law of the jungle is the natural law of this planet. That law says that if an operator can, it has the right to do. The Temporal RIghts paradigm is thus a view of rights as they really are exercised and, therefore, the simplest and most honest view of natural rights.

This demonstrates the need for a principle that will civilize us, and we find that in the simple “all men are created equal [in value]” principle. The morality needed is simply that your rights end where mine begin. Otherwise, I am your slave.

The Temporal Rights paradigm leads to the principle that good is honoring, respecting, and protecting natural rights, and evil is any violation of those rights, whether by law or person. Can you think of an evil that is not such a violation? This morality is powerful because it is simple. And it forms a bases for jurisprudence.

A Paradigm Shift for Jurisprudence

The usual view of crime sets a perpetrator against a victim, but under the light of Temporal RIghts all conlicts are seen as a conflict of rights. This is a paradigmatic shift that balances the process of jurisprudence by simultaneously recognizing the natural rights of both parties. Temporal Rights establishes an objective view rather than a moral supremecy/guilt view of crime. This promises to usher in a higher form of justice that will reduce or eliminate the feeling that justice was incomplete. This often arises when a victim has rights that were ignored during a trial. This new paradigm could lead to a sentence for both the parties by addressing all the rights that were infringed. The victim might need to change some things too.

Jurisprudence cannot be even-handed while crudely casting conflict in the simplistic framework of perpetrator/victim.

Realizing that natural rights have a natural hierarchy, I have begun a search for a way to place them in their proper order. I have discovered a method that needs much work but seems promising. It is described in Boundaries of the Temporal RIghts Hierarchy. These can be used in jurisprudence as an aid in balancing the rights of the plaintiff and the defendant because they demonstrate types of rights and their relative weights.

Overcoming Nihilism

The “scientific” thinkers have all but conquered our civilization and are hell-bent on returning us to the pagan state the desert religions saved us from. They happily celebrate the death of God with their hedonism and perversions that, for example, are sacrificing children to the god of convenience and sexual slavery they call freedom. They don’t seem to realize that they are fundamentally claiming to be the center of the moral universe.

The Temporal Rights perspective offers a completely secular origin for the natural rights that they cannot violate without revealing their crass selfishness.

The Temporal Rights concept goes even further. If the highest power of man is the ability to separate stimulus and response and thus to choose, then the highest choice must be the choice to love.

The Spiritual Component of Temporal Rights

When the American Indian needed and saw a buffalo, he saw two things simultaneously: a wonderful resource and a divine creature. Many of these people thought it was necessary to explain to the animal what was going to happen and why. Some even thought that unless this kind of respect was afforded an animal or plant the power and/or healing/nourishment would not be experienced.

Paiute Religion Placard
Placard in the Kaibab Band of Paiute Indians Museum, Pipe Spring National Monument, Fredonia, Arizona

This connection of rights and powers is central to this viewpoint. “Within Paiute philosophy, plants, animals, mountains, rocks, and water are viewed as intertwined, and each has a significant purpose to the connectedness of life in this land. All natural objects are seen as having … power that can help if used in a correct and reverent way.” Thus Temporal RIghts offers a graceful path from the physical to the spiritual.

In fact, we may someday discover that even this viewpoint is upside down: that the primal thing is the authority of rights, and that they gave rise to their physical embodiment. Just a thought that I cannot fully comprehend.

An Invitation

Mascot Owl Right Wing Extended

Several years ago, I decided to look for natural rights within natural law. It seemed obvious to me that the two had to be intimately connected: that the ontology of natural rights ought to be found in the nature of nature. In fear that any study of existing natural rights theories might prejudice my mind and preclude my hoped-for discovery, I avoided them altogether. I ignored the masters in hopes that I might surpass them.

I began the search based on an experience I had almost a half-century ago. While writing On Human Rights and Government, the second essay of the Bicentennial feature series for The Freeman magazine published by the Foundation for Economic Education (FEE), I wanted to provide a basis for those rights that would be at least palatable to non-believers. I didn’t know a basis that was not some religious or secular version of “endowed by their Creator,” so I apologetically prayed for one.

A concept immediately came to mind showing the hierarchy of rights demonstrated by a beaver cutting down a tree, and a tree splitting a rock. The essence of this was that they had the right to do what they were doing. The property right of the stone was particularly compelling to me because it demonstrated the inalienability of rights so profoundly: you either have a rock with a property right or you have neither. I liked the fact that this was all within the domain of the most fundamental principles of natural law.

While I liked that demonstration of rights, it seemed to me that it just sort of hung out there in logical space. I wanted to see if it could be anchored better or justified by finding a solid connection to the physical universe. But a connection eluded me until one night when I realized that the right and the power are one and the same, that these separate characteristics only appeared when an object was examined through one or the other lens. Their profound intrinsicality had escaped me until then.

It is a new and unprecedented paradigm, and I invite anyone who can find a problem with Temporal Rights to please help me fine tune (or abandon) the idea. If you happen to be one who disagrees, PLEASE state your reasons in a comment below. It is new and virtually untested so –

We rarely think of this fact, but it is true that our freedom in based on the idea of rights. There is no other basis. So if you think Temporal RIghts might be a strength to freedom, help me get the word out.

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *